Friday, September 27, 2013
Saturday, August 17, 2013
GROUNDWORK OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS
THE
DISCUSSION BELOW CAME FROM VARIOUS SOURCES THROUGH WHICH I AM INDEBTED;
NONETHELESS, THE DISCUSSION THAT FOLLOWS IS PRIMARILY BASED ON THE MAIN TEXT OF
THE SCHOLAR IMMANUEL KANT'S "GROUNDWORK OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS
(GERMAN: Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten)"
A person who fruitfully resists the
temptation of desire has willpower ( willpower means a combination
of determination and self-discipline that enables somebody to do something
despite the difficulties involved) while the individual who gives in and
acts to satisfy the desire does not have willpower.
This concept of willpower brings to
mind the following model of human action: The agent begins with a group of
beliefs and desires that are motives or reasons to action. Motives
to action are like forces that get the body into action. The agent,
however, must (or at least should) evaluate the desires to determine whether
they should or shouldn’t be satisfied. The agent’s reason acts as
the evaluator. When reason acts as evaluator, reason is also
considered governor, because it is the last thing that determines the will
(will means the part of the mind with which somebody consciously
decides things; the use of the mind to make decisions about things; the
determination to do something or a desire or inclination to do something),
which in turn determines action. Before a particular desire can be acted on by
the agent, the act of willing to attempt to satisfy the desire must first
exist. The agent needs needs to choose or decide to either act
or not act on the desire. Only then does the body act. Hence,
we could imagine human action schematically in the following manner:
Beliefs + desires → evaluation of
reason → Act of will to satisfy desire (decision)
→
Action to satisfy desire.
In any event that reason is not acting
as evaluator, the model turns into something like this:
Beliefs
+ desires → Act of will to satisfy desire (decision) → Action to
satisfy desire.
Immanuel Kant acknowledged that
desires often conflict. There are instances that acting to satisfy one desire
will ensure that we cannot satisfy another desire. Let us say for example that
you have the desire to go out with friends this coming Saturday to dance and
party. Satisfying now this desire would mean sacrificing your other
desire to jump to bed early and maximize the highly recommended hours of sleep
of 7 to 8 hours a day. Take again for example the given situation,
you have the desire to play DOTA or to have an EB with someone else you have
been chatting lately over the net after your class this afternoon; however, you
also have the desire to read something about Immanuel Kant’s life so that you
will not be getting a failing score in your quiz in this subject next
meeting. In such instances where we have with us conflicting
desires, we must decide which desire to satisfy.
As rational individuals, it is
expected on our part that we have to let our reason decide between conflicting
desires (but sometimes, as individuals with organic or earthly bodies with
organic or earthly desires and needs, we oftentimes find ourselves consumed in
satisfying our base desires. I am not saying this as an excuse but we should at
least now how to master our desires as rational individuals…I hope you still
remember “the mark of virtue” of Aristotle). No particular action
will be done until our will has been activated. Hence, our will is
considered to be the master of our actions. According to Immanuel
Kant, if we are rational, then our will must not be the slave of our desires by
merely doing the request or command of our desires. Our will instead
can cooperate with our reason to master whatever desires we have.
The only
thing that is good without qualification or restriction is a good will. A good
will alone is good in all circumstances and in that sense is an absolute good
or unconditioned good. The goodness of a good will is not derived
from the goodness of the results which it produces. A good will
continues to have its own uniqueness goodness even where, by some misfortune,
it is unable to produce the results at which it aims. As Kant would say in
the Groundwork, “it would still shine like a jewel for its own sake
as something which has its full value in itself” (see your reading for further
emphasis on this point of Kant on the good will and its result).
In going further with his discussion on the good will, Kant in the Groundwork tried to discuss the function of reason. According to Kant, reason has been imparted to us as a practical power─that is, as one which is to have influence on the will; the true function of reason must be to produce a will which is good, not as a means to some further end, but in itself….(see your reading for further emphasis on this point of Kant on the function of reason). For Kant, reason in action has for him two main functions, the first of which has to be subordinated to the second. The first function is to secure the individual’s own happiness (a conditioned good), while the second is to manifest a will that is good in itself.
However, despite these discussions made by Kant, a question comes to mind─that is, if one thing that is good without qualifications is a good will, then what makes will good and what makes it bad?
Kant was a supporter of what we have called commonsense morality. He thought that the moral views common to most people are pretty much correct. Therefore, he would think that a person with a good will would not commit major moral offenses such as murder or robbery, would not commit minor moral offenses such as maliciously gossiping about people, and would help people in need.
Kant took these things for granted. But he recognized that a person might have a good will and not to be able to actually do any of the things a good person would do, or refrain from doing the things a good person would not do, similarly, someone might do all the things that a good person would do and refrain from doing all the things that a good person would not do, and yet not have a good will. For example, someone may contribute to charity only because it’s in his self-interest, perhaps a politician who believes that he will gain votes by (publicly) contributing to charity. Kant does not think that his contributing money shows that he has a good will.
What about performing actions that normally would be considered an indication that someone lacks a good will? Suppose someone acts n a way that is deeply offensive or insulting to someone else. Would that necessarily show that he or she lacks a good will? No- not if he or she did not intent to offensive or insulting.
Kant points out that we cannot tell whether someone has a good will by looking only at what that person does or does not do, or only at the effects or consequences of his actions. One’s intentions are the key to whether one has good will. It is what one wants to accomplish – what one wills – that counts (for the Utilitarian philosopher Jeremy Bentham, it is the consequence of the act that counts while for Immanuel Kant, it is not the consequence of the act that counts but the intention of the person doing the act). A person has a good will if he or she tires to do what is right and tries to avoid doing what is wrong. But the trying must be a genuine trying a summoning of all one’s capacities to work hard toward doing what is right and to refrain from doing what’s wrong (if by this time you now have in mind this question of what is right and what is wrong, then such question will be answered as we proceed with our discussion).
Kant says that the concept of duty contains the concepts of a good will but it probably would be more accurate to say that the concept of a good will entails the concept of duty (a duty is an obligation of behavior or conduct in relation to others or even to God which has a stronger claim on a person than (he)r self-interest). One has a good will if one tries to do one’s duty. But Kant emphasized that for a will to be truly good, it must try to do its duty from purely moral motive, rather than from a self-interested movie. The purely moral motive is the desire to do one’s duty out of respect for the moral law. A person with a good will respects the moral law and tries to act dutifully because he or she desires to act in ways that conform to what (he)r duties are.
In introducing the concept of duty, Kant came up with 3 propositions about morality rooted on duty: (1) A human action is morally good, not because it is done from immediate inclination─still less because it is done from self-interest─but because it is done fro the sake of duty (Consider the implication of this situation, what if for example in this particular room at around 7 pm in the evening, I saw you desperately in need for immediate medical attention but then the problem is I am not disposed this time to help; likewise, I have a business deal to attend to at 7:15 pm to have this 4 million pesos account deal to be safely deposited to my account.); (2) An action done from duty has moral worth, not from the results it attains or seeks to attain, but from a formal principle or maxim─the principle of doing one’s duty whatever that duty may be (This simply re-states the first proposition in a more technical way. We have already seen that a good will cannot derive its unconditioned goodness from the conditioned goodness of the results at which it aims, and this is true also of the morally good actions in which a good will acting for the sake of duty is manifested.); (3) Duty is the necessity to act out of reverence for the law (What is this law? This law speaks a a law which is valid for all rational beings as such independently of their particular desires. This law is better understood with the Categorical Imperative of Kant as a test of maxim by helping us evaluate whether or not a maxim is possible to become a universal law.).
ACTIONS AND MAXIMS
Kant believed that people acts as they do for
the reason (whether or not they are immediately conscious of the reason or
engage in deliberation before acting). For example, suppose that Marc and
Andrew each contribute PHP 100,000 to charity. According to Kant, each has a
reason for his or her action. Let’s assume that we know their reasons. Marc
approves of the goals of the charity and wants to help in accomplishing its
goals. Andrew knows that the names of large contributors will be
publicized; he wants to impress his business associates and customers, which he
thinks will improve his business.
Kant believed that when people act for a
reason, they’re following a maxim – a kind of personal rule of action. Of
course, people do not always consciously formulate maximum and then
deliberately follow them. Rather, people often act as though they formulate and
follow maxims. However, Kant seemed to assume that we can discover what maxim
will follow, even if we did not consciously formulate and follow it. Given Marc
and Andrew's reasons for contributing to charity, we might express the maxims
they were following as M1 (Marc’s Maxim) and M2 (Adrew’s maxim.)
M1. I will contribute to charity when I approved of the
Charity’s goal, and I want to help it achieve its purpose.
M2. I will contribute to charity when I think that doing
so will help improve my business and I want to improve my business.
A maxim takes the form “I will do action X in
circumstances C for purpose P.” It is a personal principal of action, a
kind of prescription of how a person will act in certain circumstances to
achieve what he or she wants. Thus, a maxim must specify: (1) what I will
do, (2) the concrete circumstances in which I will do it, and (3) why I will do
it.
According to Kant, an action done from duty
has moral worth based only on the maxim that the agent follows, which specified
the action, the circumstances and the motive. But surely an action cannot have
moral worth if the agent is following a bad maxim, such as “I will kill people whenever
it is advantageous to me.” Presumably an action has moral worth if and only if
the maxim being followed is a morally acceptable maxim. But what makes a maxim
morally acceptable or morally unacceptable?
Before turning to this question, however, let
us reflect a bit more on the maxims and behavior of Marc and Andrew. Did Marc
or Andrew do anything wrong in contributing to charity? If they were following
morally unacceptable maxims, then they were doing something wrong, but if they
were following morally acceptable maxims, they were not doing anything wrong.
Whether they did anything wrong, then it all depends on whether their maxims
are morally acceptable. Surely neither did anything wrong. However, Kant would
say that Andrew’s action lacked moral worth because the maxim he followed was
purely self-interested. (Lacking moral worth, their actions do not merit
praise; but it does not follow that because they lack moral worth, they merit
condemnation instead) so once again, we face the task of distinguishing between
morally acceptable and morally unacceptable maxims.
Thus, whether we are talking about the moral
worth of actions or the rightness and wrongness of actions, we need to
distinguish between morally acceptable and morally unacceptable maxims. We
require a test of maxims that will enable us to distinguish between those that
are and those that are not morally acceptable to act on.
Kant did not think that we need to invent a
totally new test to determine the rightness and wrongness of maxims. He
believed that there is a test that most ordinary people apply and that has been
endorsed by most of the world’s major religions, including
Christianity. This test is the so-called Golden Rule: Treat people
the way you want to be treated. However, he did think that the Gold
Rule needed to be made more precise in order to be applied correctly. He called
his reformulation of the Golden Rule the Categorical Imperative. It’s
an imperative because it takes the form of a rule.
It’s categorical because it applies in all
circumstances, regardless of an agents’ desires and because it binds all
rational agents.
5 FORMULATIONS OF THE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE:
(1) The Formula of Universality or the Principle of Universal Law
"Act only on that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it should be come a universal law."
(2) The Formula of the Law of Nature
"Act as if the maxim of your action were to become through your will as a universal law of nature without contradiction."
(3) The Respect for People Formulation or The Principle of an End in Itself
"Act in such a way that you always treat humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, never simply as a means but always at the same time as an end."
(4) The Formula on Autonomy or The Principle of Freedom (Freedom of Will as Rational Agents)
"So act that your will can regard itself at the same time as making universal law through its maxim."
(5) The Formula of the Kingdom of Ends
"So act as if you were through your maxims a law-making member of a kingdom of ends."
Can your maxim be universalized without contradiction?
Can your maxim show respect to yourself as a person and to other persons as well?
If your answer is NO, then your maxim cannot become a moral law.
In the application of the rule on contradiction, you have to consider if in the process your happiness or your own survival or existence or humanity's survival would be at sake or compromised. At this point, it is important to point out that for Immanuel Kant, committing suicide to escape the challenges and sufferings in life is not morally acceptable because this maxim can never be universalized without contradiction aside from the fact that committing suicide will not also show respect to oneself as a person since the self is sacrificed to achieve an end which is to run away from those challenges and sufferings.
In the application of the rule on contradiction, you have to consider if in the process your happiness or your own survival or existence or humanity's survival would be at sake or compromised. At this point, it is important to point out that for Immanuel Kant, committing suicide to escape the challenges and sufferings in life is not morally acceptable because this maxim can never be universalized without contradiction aside from the fact that committing suicide will not also show respect to oneself as a person since the self is sacrificed to achieve an end which is to run away from those challenges and sufferings.
Take note that in the kingdom or in the World of Ends, one has either a price or a dignity or intrinsic value or unconditioned value. If it has a price, then something else can be put in its place as equivalent. If it is exalted above all price and so admits of no equivalent, then it has a dignity.
Autonomy or Freedom is the ground or the cornerstone of the dignity of human nature and of every rational nature. Dignity must be viewed as the result of people who are free and autonomous moral and rational agents mutually respecting each other.
Ang paggamit ng kapwa natin tao ay hindi tahasan at agad-agarang masama. Kailangan nating alamin kung ano ang pamamaraan at kung paano natin gagamitin ang iba. Do you just treat the other person as a thing? Hipocrito ang taong magsasabing hindi ako nanggamit at hindi ako mangagamit ng iba. No one will ever continue living/surviving without (he)r using others or being used in return. We all live in communities and societies where we all are functionally related to one another because of necessity. Hindi lahat ng pangangailangan mo ay kaya mong ibigay sa iyong sarili.
|
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)